From The Accidental Activist.
Most people believe that adult
humans are moral beings, capable of acting not from instinct but rather from a
reasoned set of rules. These rules are generally called “ethics.” For most of
history, discussion of “ethical rules” was dominated first by superstition and
later by religious doctrine. Because most people weren’t able to read, they
were reliant on leaders (tribal, religious, etc.) to tell them what to believe.
Thus, ethics were largely devoid of serious reasoned examination. Only in the
last few centuries have ethics been rigorously pursued outside of religious
doctrine. In many countries today, even individuals who hold strong religious
convictions are dependent upon arguments from secular ethics to resolve
disagreements, and most religious doctrines now accept that their texts should
be viewed critically as products, at least in part, of human cultures.
Pope
John Paul II stated that religious principles must hold up to rational ethical
argument if they are valid. In other words, he granted that no one should take
any ethical principles “on faith.” Any student of theology knows that religious
texts were clearly created by humans in a specific time and place. Whatever we
take from these writings will require historical and ethical analysis, rather
than an uncritical read. It’s a good thing, too, or what would we do with
sections like these?
When your brother is
reduced to poverty and sells himself to you, you shall not use him to work for
you as a slave. . . . Such slaves as you have, male or female, shall come from
the nations round about you; from them you may buy slaves. You may also buy the
children of those who have settled and lodge with you and such of their family
as are born in the land. These may become your property, and you may leave them
to your sons after you; you may use them as slaves permanently (Leviticus 25: 39–46).
While the Israelites
were in the desert, a man was discovered gathering wood on the Sabbath day.
Those who caught him at it brought him to Moses and Aaron and the whole
assembly. But they kept him in custody, for there was no clear decision as to
what should be done with him. Then the LORD said to Moses, “This man shall be
put to death; let the whole community stone him outside the camp.” So the whole
community led him outside the camp and stoned him to death, as the LORD had
commanded Moses (Numbers 15: 32–46).
There are many similar examples
from the Bible, used for millennia to justify the Crusades, witch burnings,
slavery, child abuse, denial to women of the right to vote, condemnation of
homosexuals, and so on. In every case, the Bible was used to justify the wrong
side of history, as admirably discussed in Ernie Bringas’s exploration of the
issue, Going by the Book: Past and
Present Tragedies of Biblical Authority.
If a Jew or a
Christian claims their religious texts are an infallible guide to morality,
they would have to say that slavery is ethically acceptable, working on the
Sabbath warrants the death penalty, and so on. Alternatively, if one does not
consider a literal reading of a religious text as the first, last, and only
word on ethics, then one is left to find another, rational basis for ethics. To
reduce the problem of interpretation and the prevalence of inherent prejudices,
one might do well to seek a universal basis that can transcend the boundaries
of faith and culture. Of course, seeking such a universal basis is not at odds
with developed religious belief; any Creator who has given humans the ability
for rational thought and logical analysis would want us to use these abilities.
Despite
the capacity for rationality, human beings have several significant obstacles
to overcome when discussing ethics. Foremost, we have significant evolutionary
baggage that leads us to value ourselves and family first, our tribe second,
and strangers third—if we value them at all (Druyan and Sagan, 1993; Wright,
1995). Some people call this hierarchical value system our “moral intuition,”
or our “moral instinct”—what “feels” or “seems” right is right (i.e., ethical). Some philosophers derive ethics from our
instincts and intuitions. Intuitionists may judge ethical arguments against our
intuitions and modify these arguments so as to fit better with our intuitions.
Still other philosophers start with their intuitions and work backwards to try
to create some seemingly rational basis to justify their desired conclusions.
Not everyone has
the same instincts about ethics, however, and many instincts are contradictory,
and thus cannot all be valid. Indeed, we now widely condemn as unethical the
instincts of those who enslaved blacks, burned witches, forced children to work
in mines, and so on. We are convinced that a century from now, people will
condemn our generation for instincts we may now be harboring uncritically. It
is important that ethics, whenever possible, avoid deferring to potentially
prejudiced instincts.
Universal Ethics
The easiest means by which to avoid
our prejudices is to take as an objective a point of view when discussing
ethics as we possibly can. Such a point of view is sometimes called “the point
of view of the universe,” a view that allows us to empathize with all those
beings affected by a decision. One of the more common methods of approximating
this view is called “The Original Position.” Imagine yourself as a disembodied
entity, existing outside the world. At some unknown time in the future, you
will be “incarnated” on Earth, at which point you will take on the intellectual
and emotional characteristics of your new body. In addition, you do not know
your future IQ, your race, your nationality, your gender, or even your species. (Although most philosophers don’t include species variation in
this calculation, they haven’t given a good reason for species to be excluded.)
Behind
this “veil of ignorance,” (a concept created by Harvard philosopher John
Rawls), you must choose what is to be held good and bad in the world in which
you will be incarnated: i.e., what rules of ethics should be followed. Because
you are self-interested, you want to protect whatever interests you may have in
your various possible incarnations. Put another way, a universal view like that
of the Original Position involves an “equal consideration of interests” of all
those beings one could become.
How
can one think about a situation like this? What can be said about the various
beings whose lives we could possibly lead? How can we compare their diverse
interests? One universal aspect is that every being said to possess “interests”
seems to pursue experiences that they find desirable (pleasure) while avoiding
those that are undesirable (pain)—in short, maximizing pleasure while
minimizing pain are interests held by each individual with the biological
capacity for having interests. Such interests appear to be fundamental to all
conscious creatures, likely the result of evolutionary processes that used
pleasure and pain as inducements to guide behavior and learning. If organisms
(such as bacteria, plants, and most likely some simpler animals like clams and
some other invertebrates) are incapable of the subjective experience of
pleasure or pain, then the rules by which one interacts with them are
irrelevant to them. You could be
incarnated as an oak tree, but the universal system of ethics set forth would
be inconsequential to you.
For sentient,
conscious beings capable of subjective experiences, these interests vary as
widely as the organisms do: from basic avoidance of nerve tissue damage, to the
conscious, intellectual desire for “justice.” What seems likely to be
universal, however, is that vertebrate animals are aware of pain and pleasure
(Bateson, 1992).
Pleasure
and pain thus provide a universal basis for ethics in which the interests of
diverse beings can be compared. Knowing nothing more than this, one can set
forth a basic ethical rule for the world into which they will be incarnated: A
conscious being’s interests in a pleasurable, minimally painful life will be
respected as much as the comparable interests of other beings. In short: equal
consideration of interests.
Differences of Interests
Equal consideration of interests
does not imply equality of treatment. Individuals have different interests and
thus require different treatment to protect these interests. As Richard Ryder
points out (using the language of rights), “humans suffer if denied the right
to vote, so this is important for humans but it is not so for other species.
Access to eucalyptus leaves is, however, important for koalas, and so the right
of access to eucalyptus leaves is an important right for them.”
Furthermore,
not all interests are of the same intensity. As Bernard Rollin writes: “I would
not adopt as a universal principle always favoring the ‘higher’ animals for
example, if the choice came down to a quick death for the higher animal versus
a slow, lingering death for a lower animal, one should presumably choose the
death of the higher animal. This makes us realize that we need to consider not
only number of interests, but also
quality and intensity of their satisfaction and frustration.”
Similarly,
our interest in finding pleasure and avoiding pain may not be equal. It is
possible for an individual to have a variety of pleasurable experiences, but
the range of pleasures in life does not seem to match the range of pains. As
Ryder writes, “At its extreme, pain is more powerful than pleasure can ever be.
Pain overrules pleasure within the individual far more effectively than
pleasure can dominate pain.” Some will balk at this, but think of the most
pleasurable experience you’ve ever had. Most people can easily come up with a
list of experiences that they wouldn’t be willing to endure in order to
experience that pleasure (e.g., various forms of torture, watching a loved one die
a terrible death, etc.). In other words, there are limitless unpleasant
experiences that you would not suffer in order to have even the most intense
possible pleasure. All this isn’t to say that pleasure doesn’t count at all,
but that, in general, equal consideration of interests focuses on the reduction
and elimination of suffering.
Applications
Once we’ve arrived at the view of
equal consideration of interests and see that pleasure and pain form a common
currency with which to compare these interests, we must ask what this means for
our ethics. First, it will take us to many of the conventional ethical
positions that most of us already accept: suffering is bad; hunger and disease
should be alleviated; people should be given personal freedoms with which to
prosper; individuals shouldn’t be discriminated against on the basis of their
race, gender, nationality, sexual preference, or other group membership; laws
should protect the interests of the weaker against the stronger.
However, our view
of equal consideration also leads us to some conclusions that run counter to
current conventional ethics, particularly with regard to non-human animals. If
suffering matters, then much of our current treatment of animals is
unjustifiable. For instance, we may gain some pleasure from eating a fish or
chicken sandwich. However, equal consideration of interests makes us put
ourselves in the place of the animal as well as in the place of the
sandwich-eater. Does the pleasure of eating a fish or chicken sandwich—instead of a veggie burger or other
vegetarian option—outweigh the pain we would endure to be raised and killed for
that sandwich? If we were incarnated as a chicken or farmed fish, we would
conclude that the interest in not being abused and slaughtered is stronger than
the pleasure gained by eating a meat sandwich instead of a veggie burger.
Objections
The universality of this “equal
consideration of interests” theory of ethics is straightforward. The sole
logical, rational, and reasonable manner for building a truly universal ethic
is by including everyone with interests, including other animals. What is
important is determined only by the nature of, and consequences for, those
affected by decisions. Yet instincts and prejudices are far older than
formalized ethics, and run as deep as our evolution. Thus, it may be worthwhile
to examine some of the objections against universalized ethics.
Excluding
Animals: Moral Contracts
One objection is that the pool of
possible incarnates includes those unable to act from the chosen code of
ethics—such as children, the mentally handicapped, and most non-human animals.
In other words, “in order to have rights, you must also have duties.” This is a
basic “moral contract” theory. Some “contractualists” argue that anyone who
cannot also have duties does not deserve direct moral consideration. Is this
reasonable?
Given
that infants, children, etc., can be affected by the decisions of moral agents,
there’s no consistent reason for excluding them from the pool of possible
incarnates, and thus from consideration of their interests. It would be in the
interests of those in the original position to include these states within
their code of ethics, since all moral agents begin life unable to participate
in any moral contract (as infants and children) and can become that way (after
a stroke or senility). As Rollin concludes, “In a nutshell, there is no
argument showing that only moral agents can be moral recipients. On the
contractualist view, it is also hard to see why animals differ in a morally
relevant way from all sorts of humans who can’t rationally enter into
contracts—infants, children (especially terminally ill children, who will not
live long enough to actualize rationality), the retarded, the comatose, the
senescent, the brain-damaged, the addicted, the compulsive, the sociopath, all
of whom are also incapable of entering into or respecting contracts.”
Moreover,
it’s not even clear that the distinction between moral agents and others would
exclude all nonhuman animals. While a handful of adult humans may claim a
monopoly on ethical theory, humans do
not have a monopoly on ethical practices.
As Drs. Carl Sagan and Ann Druyan relate in Shadows
of Forgotten Ancestors:
In a laboratory setting, macaques were fed if they were willing to pull a chain and electrically shock an unrelated macaque whose agony was in plain view through a one-way mirror. Otherwise, they starved. After learning the ropes, the monkeys frequently refused to pull the chain; in one experiment only 13% would do so; 87% preferred to go hungry. One macaque went without food for nearly two weeks rather than hurt its fellow. Macaques who had themselves been shocked in previous experiments were even less willing to pull the chain. The relative social status or gender of the macaques had little bearing on their reluctance to hurt others.
If asked to choose between the human
experimenters offering the macaques this Faustian bargain and the macaques
themselves suffering from real hunger rather than causing pain to others, our
own moral sympathies do not lie with the scientists. But their experiments
permit us to glimpse in non-humans a saintly willingness to make sacrifices in
order to save others—even those who are not close kin. By conventional human
standards, these macaques—who have never gone to Sunday school, never heard of
the Ten Commandments, never squirmed through a single junior high school civics
lesson—seem exemplary in their moral grounding and their courageous resistance
to evil. Among these macaques, at least in this case, heroism is the norm. If
the circumstances were reversed, and captive humans were offered the same deal
by macaque scientists, would we do as well? (Especially when there is an
authority figure urging us to administer the electric shocks, we humans are
disturbingly willing to cause pain and for a reward much more paltry than food
is for a starving macaque [cf. Stanley Milgram, Obedience to Authority: An Experimental Overview].) In human
history there are a precious few whose memory we revere because they knowingly
sacrificed themselves for others. For each of them, there are multitudes who
did nothing.
Discussing the macaque monkeys who
chose to starve rather than inflict pain on another, Drs. Sagan and Druyan
conclude, “Might we have a more optimistic view of the human future if we were
sure our ethics were up to their standards?”
Excluding
Animals: Rationality
People are generally willing to
include all humans (including babies, the insane, etc.) in their circle of
ethics, but balk at a truly universal ethic (i.e., the inclusion of non-human
animals in the pool of possible incarnates). This is because of the obvious and
difficult implications, notably that one should not eat or generally cause
animals to suffer. Many find the consequences of this inclusion unacceptable,
and it’s to avoid these consequences that the vast majority of philosophers and
ethicists have either simply ignored animals or created arguments trying to
show that only humans require ethical consideration.
Is it possible to
build a rational and morally relevant argument for the exclusion of animals
instead of simply including everyone in the Original Position? Despite the
efforts of many, it is unclear how one might do this. For instance, in his book
A Theory of Justice, John Rawls argues that only moral agents are to be
included. Rawls attempts to count children among moral agents because they are potential moral agents. However, as
Singer writes, this is “an ad hoc
device confessedly designed to square his theory with our ordinary moral
intuitions, rather than something for which independent arguments can be
produced. Moreover, although Rawls admits that those with irreparable mental
defects ‘may present a difficulty,’ he offers no suggestions towards the
solution of this difficulty” (Practical
Ethics).
What
is it about being rational that makes it ethically relevant for inclusion in
the set of potential incarnates? Of course, rationality is an assumption for an
analysis of the Original Position, for there’d be no discussion otherwise (if
irrational decisions were allowed, anything would be fair game, and there’d be
no basis for a set of rules governing interactions). Yet making rationality a
requirement for being a potential
incarnate has no basis. If rationality were a prerequisite, many “marginal”
human beings (such as the brain-damaged and senile) would be excluded from
moral consideration. Although there’s nothing to indicate that, as biological
beings, rationality is inherent even in theory.
Excluding
Animals: Intelligence
Intelligence is often offered as
the function that sets humans apart from other animals. Rollin counters this
common contention:
But why does intelligence score highest? Ultimately,
perhaps, because intelligence allows us to control, vanquish, dominate, and
destroy all other creatures. If this is the case, it is power that puts us on
top of the pyramid. But if power provides grounds for including or excluding
creatures from the scope of moral concern, we have essentially accepted the
legitimacy of the thesis that “might makes right” and have, in a real sense,
done away with all morality altogether. If we do accept this thesis, we cannot
avoid extending it to people as well, and it thus becomes perfectly moral for
Nazis to exterminate the Jews, muggers to prey on old people, the majority to
oppress the minority, and the government to do as it sees fit to any of us.
Furthermore, as has often been pointed out, it follows from this claim that if
an extraterrestrial alien civilization were intellectually, technologically,
and militarily superior to us, it would be perfectly justified in enslaving or
eating or exterminating human beings.
Or to quote the founder of
utilitarian thought, Jeremy Bentham, in discussing what it is that qualifies
one to be worthy of moral concern: “Is it the faculty of reason, or, perhaps,
the faculty of discourse? But a full-grown horse or dog is beyond comparison a
more rational, as well as a more conversable animal, than an infant of a day,
or a week, or even a month, old. But suppose the case were otherwise, what
would it avail? The question is not, ‘Can they reason?’ nor, ‘Can they talk?’
but, ‘Can they suffer?’”
Indeed
Bentham’s point is well taken, although, more and more, scientists are learning
that animals are interesting individuals with rich intellectual lives. We now
know that pigs function intellectually at a very high level (by some measures,
beyond that of your average human three-year-old), and chickens have certain
capacities beyond that of a child of one. Pigs can learn from one another, play
video games, and more; chickens have the capacity for foresight, delayed
gratification, and the ability to figure out the existence of an object they
can’t see.
But in practice,
humans don’t make ethical decisions based on a hierarchy of intelligence. For
the same reason that most people bring their family dog or cat into their realm
of moral concern—they understand the animal as an individual—there’s no reason
to exclude other animals either. Or, as Charles Darwin put it, “There is no
fundamental difference between man and the higher animals in their mental
faculties. . . . The lower animals, like man, manifestly feel pleasure and
pain, happiness, and misery.”
Excluding
Animals: Language
R. G. Frey (Interests and Rights: The Case Against Animals) argues that only
with language can a creature have interests: “If what is believed is that a
certain declarative sentence is true, then no creature which lacks language can
have beliefs; and without beliefs, a creature cannot have desires. And this is
the case with animals, or so I suggest; and if I am right, not even in the
sense, then, of wants or desires do animals have interests.”
Let’s
assume for a moment that animals don’t have language and see if the argument
would hold up to rigorous scrutiny: While quick to use this rationalization
against animals, Frey ignores the implication for infants and brain damaged humans.
(Furthermore, without beliefs and interests, why and how would infants acquire
language?) Still others, such as Michael Leahy, will go so far as to allow for
the exclusion of “marginal humans,” so as to be able to reject consideration
for other animals! Indeed, given that fully matured Broca and Wernke areas of
the brain are required for language, if Frey were to have a minor stroke in one
of these areas, he would no longer be subject to ethical consideration, and,
based on his argument, could be subsequently eaten or used for experiments,
regardless of the suffering he experienced. It seems safe to say that Frey has
never experienced severe pain, or else he’d know that language isn’t required
to have interests, as the deepest sufferings often overwhelm the ability to
think in language.
This
isn’t to imply that the brain is not required to have interests. Damage to the
brain can lead to the loss of interests—thus the term “brain dead.” Even
relatively small damage, such as the destruction of the hypothalamus in the
case of Karen Ann Quinlan, who lived for many years in a persistent vegetative
state, can end one’s interests.
What
does speaking represent? Does language create an entirely new (inner) world—one
alien to different from those without language (infants, animals)? Did Koko,
the ape who learned sign language, become a wholly new creature? At what point
in learning a language does an infant have an interest in not being tortured? A bigger question is this: Before Koko
learned a form of human language, did she perhaps have another form of
language, one we couldn’t understand? It begs credulity to think otherwise, as
we continue to learn about communication in other mammals (including rodents),
in birds, and in fish. Dr. Temple Grandin, in her book Animals in Translation: Using the Mysteries of Autism
to Decode Animal Behavior,
points out that science has always started from the premise that other
animals can’t do certain things, and then learned
that, in fact, they can. She notes that every time we assume they can’t (use
tools, plan ahead, learn from one another or from humans, and so on), we
discover that we were wrong. If experiments have failed to show as much, it
turns out that it was the experimenters who were failing, not the animals.
Excluding Animals: Our Interests Are More Important
One might allow that many non-human
animals have interests, but find no inherent implications from this admission.
Indeed, few call for outright and total dismissal of animals’ concerns (e.g.,
advocating the repeal of current welfare and anti-cruelty laws). Rather, the
current Western consensus is that humans’ interests are simply more important. But to whom are humans’
interests more important? To humans,
of course. But do we really contend that our potential interest in eating a
chicken nugget instead of a vegetarian option is greater than the chickens’
desire not to be drugged, cooped in their own waste, transported through all
weather extremes, and cruelly slaughtered?
Defenders of
animal experimentation often use emotional hypothetical choices of “more
important” to defend animal exploitation. For example, concerning her daughter
Claire, who has cystic fibrosis, Jane McCabe wrote in Newsweek (December 26, 1988): “If you had to choose between saving
a cute dog or my equally cute, blond, brown-eyed daughter, whose life would you
choose?. . . It’s not that I don’t love animals, it’s that I love Claire more.”
Ignoring that a single dog experiment could never cure her child’s disease, the
moral question is whether personal attachment justifies harming others. Since
McCabe probably loves her daughter more than other children, would she endorse
experimenting on other children to save her child? This, after all, would be a
scientifically more productive research strategy than experimenting on nonhuman
animals.
Prejudice Is Prejudice
Throughout history, people have set
forth systems of rules and laws which excluded others: other clans, other
races, other sexes, other religions, etc. To current Western observers, many of
these prejudices seem as self-evidently “wrong” as the current exclusion of
other species seems obviously “right.” Even if we insist on rejecting the
universal requirement of ethics, given our propensity for prejudice we should
be skeptical of any distinction based on membership of a group, and should
seriously question any rules that just happen to benefit us.
It’s an undeniable
fact that other animals are made of flesh, blood, and bone, just like human
beings. They have the same five physiological senses and a range of thought and
sensation that is often as developed as many humans. The
only clear distinction of membership in the human species is that, with gender,
race, and nationality no longer being fashionable prejudices, “human” is the
most exclusive group to which most philosophers now pledge allegiance.
This is an excellent presentation of the ethically rational case for recognising animal rights.
ReplyDelete